- Free newsletter
- The Latest
- Topics
-
About
Is existence enough? Don't donor-conceived kids have rights?
Two stories concerning the donation of gametes – sperm
and ova – appeared recently in the media.
One related that a “virtual” sperm and egg bank is
being established that will only accept offers to donate from “beautiful”
people. Internet polling will determine who is beautiful enough to do so. The
goal – informed by the principle that “everyone deserves a beautiful child” –
is to enable “ugly” people to have beautiful children.
The other story was that New Zealand will possibly
allow “double donation”; that is, would-be parents would be able to use both
donated ova and sperm to create embryos (a practice that is not legally
prohibited, although still fairly uncommon, in Canada). As Diane Allen of the
Infertility Network argues, this “cannot be construed as any form of
infertility ‘treatment,’ but, rather, the deliberate manufacture of babies to
meet consumer demand.”
What do we, as a society, owe to the resulting
children, especially when we are complicit in their coming into being, by
approving and funding the technologies used to create them? They are the people
most profoundly and directly affected. They will live their lives as
“donor-conceived adults,” “genetic orphans,” as many of them call themselves.
Donor conception may be a completely avoidable human
tragedy in the making, one for which we might be holding a truth and
reconciliation commission at some future date, when offspring ask, as some are
already doing, “How could you have done this to us? How could you have allowed
this to happen?”
Is donor conception the 21st-century version of the
wrongs we now recognize we did to some children in the 20th century? Are we
repeating in a new context and in new ways the terrible errors and grave
injustices that occurred with Australia’s “stolen generation” of aboriginal
children, the United Kingdom’s “home children” sent to Canada and other British
Commonwealth countries, and the “scoop” of native children from reserves into
Canadian residential schools and white adoptive homes, all of which
deliberately separated children from their biological families.
In all these instances, our intentions, as is true in
donor conception, were to “do good.” In donor conception, however, we primarily
intend to “do good” to the adults who want a child, rather than to the child,
as was the motive – although a grossly mistaken belief – in the other
historical wrongs I have mentioned.
As an old human-rights axiom warns, an unalloyed
intention to “do good” has its dangers: “Nowhere are human rights more
threatened than when we act purporting to do only good.” Our desire to do good
can blind us to the risks and harms that are involved. Is that true of gamete
donation?
An argument that is used to support donor conception
is that the child would not exist otherwise and, therefore, should not
complain. One young donor-conceived woman, confronted with this argument,
responded, “If I were the result of rape, I would still be glad to be alive,
but that doesn’t mean I or any one else should approve of rape.”
Adoption is our longest-standing experience of dealing
with a situation where children have been intentionally disconnected from their
biological parents.
In the past, adoption records were permanently sealed.
We now recognize that as being harmful to the adopted person and potentially so
to the birth family, and unethical. Yet donor-conceived Canadians do not know
who at least one of their biological parents is, because donors here are
allowed to remain anonymous, which is no longer the case in a growing list of
countries (including Britain, Australia and New Zealand among many others).
That also is unethical and, if we continue with gamete donation, it must be
changed.
Adoptive parents were once advised by “professionals”
– as the parents of donor-conceived children have been and still often are –
not to tell their children of their origins; they were told that secrecy was
best. This, too, should be changed, not least because people excluded from a
secret that relates to them in some major way, often sense that they are being
excluded. Their not knowing what the secret is creates a situation of doubt,
which can be very difficult for them to cope with psychologically. Moreover,
such secrets can damage – sometimes even destroy – family relationships once
they come to light, as most inevitably do, often in traumatic situations (for
example, divorce or death).
Adoptive parents were also told that children were a
blank slate, that they would be just fine and would not experience loss because
of their adoptive family loving them, really “wanting them,” “going through so
much to get them” and so on. For many adopted children, even those who deeply
love their adoptive parents, this has not proved to be true, as is also the
case for some donor-conceived children. Now, prospective adoptive parents are
counselled during the home-study process to expect and accept this sense of
loss as normal.
Birth parents were told – as gamete donors are today –
that it was in their own best interests to “put it behind them and get on with
their lives,” that their relinquished children would be just fine, that they
were doing a “wonderful, selfless” thing in helping people become parents who
couldn’t otherwise do so. But this “moving on” was not always possible for the
birth parents, as is also true for some gamete donors.
I suggest that the first step in dealing, ethically,
with the issues I have identified and with other related issues, is to place
the future child, and the child’s human rights and our obligations as a society
to him or her, at the centre of the decision-making as to what should be
required, allowed or prohibited – that is, what we must, may or must not do,
respectively – in the use of assisted human reproduction technologies,
including gamete donation.
The child cannot tell us what they would consent to,
but other people conceived in these ways can. We must listen to them in order
to apply the ethical doctrine of “anticipated consent,” that is, if we cannot
reasonably assume that someone affected by our decision, who is not present,
would consent, if present, it is not ethical to proceed.
The “precautionary principle,” currently most commonly
used in environmental ethics, might also help: We should exercise wise ethical
restraint – prudence – until we are reasonably certain that it is safe and
ethical to act. And that safety goes beyond assessing only physical harm to the
future child and includes existential harm to him or her, and risk and harm to
our societal values and ethics.
What impact would wanting only beautiful children have
on our concept of unconditional parental love? Hitherto, we have believed we
love our children simply because they are our children. Does the selection and
purchase of gametes to conceive a child make the child into an object or thing,
rather than a person? How will the child feel knowing that their genetic parent
sold – and that their social parent bought – what is (as one donor-conceived
woman put it) “the essence of [their] life for $25 to a total stranger, and
then walked away without a second look back? What kind of a man sells himself
and his child so cheaply and so easily?” Is there something gravely ethically
wrong with the commercialization of the miracle of the passing on of human
life? Canadians decided there was, and that leads to yet another recent,
donor-conception news story.
In 2005, Parliament enacted the Assisted Human
Reproduction Act that made it a criminal offence to buy or sell gametes or
embryos. Assisted Human Reproduction Canada – the agency that was established
to oversee the implementation of this statute – has just been challenged with allegations
it is failing to fulfill its obligations, by not seeking prosecution of those
who take part in the continuing sale of sperm and ova in Canada.
Margaret Somerville is founding director of the Centre
for Medicine, Ethics and Law at McGill University.
Join Mercator today for free and get our latest news and analysis
Buck internet censorship and get the news you may not get anywhere else, delivered right to your inbox. It's free and your info is safe with us, we will never share or sell your personal data.
Have your say!
Join Mercator and post your comments.